Thursday, December 23, 2010

I Think Menary Missed an Argument

In the light of these remarks let’s look a little closer at Adams and Aizawa’s
account of causal-coupling to see where they have gone wrong. “If a cognitive agent causally interacts with some object in the external world in some “important” way—if that agent is coupled to an object—then that agent’s cognitive processing is constituted by processes extending into that object.” (2010b) This is precisely what I was objecting to in 2006. It assumes an already formed cognitive agent with, presumably, internal representations manipulated by computational processes, who just happens to interact with the environment. Adams and Aizawa are here leveraging their argument on a premise that I think is false—that we can consider cognitive agents independently of their environments (apart from the inputs from and outputs to the environment).
Menary thinks that we cannot consider cognitive agents independently of their environment.

But, A&A replied to this.  We think this move does not help.  Here is what we said in The Bounds of Cognition, pp. 102-3:
The suggestion appears to be that we should never think of a lone human being as a discrete cognitive system.  Humans are, so this line goes, always cognitive systems integrated into a network of interacting components.  Humans in their mere biological being are never cognitive systems.  Put more boldly, perhaps, insofar as humans are cognitive beings, they are essentially users of external vehicles.
     Suppose, just for the sake of argument, that it is true that, insofar as humans are cognitive agents, they are never entirely bereft of external vehicles that they manipulate.  That is, suppose that every human cognitive agent always engages some external vehicle or another in her cognitive processing.  Even this concession is not adequate to circumvent the coupling-constitution fallacy.  We can simply reformulate the problem to incorporate Menary’s idea.  So, suppose, simply for the sake of argument, that Otto’s biological mass never in itself suffices to form a cognitive system.  Otto’s cognitive being is always enmeshed in a network of tools.  Still, think of “young Otto” before the onset of Alzheimer’s disease.  Young Otto was embedded in one network of tools.  Presumably this network of tools will not include the notebook that will one day, say, 30 years later, be manufactured in some factory and subsequently purchased by “Old Otto” who has come to suffer from Alzheimer’s Disease.  That is, assume that ones cognition does not extend into currently non-existent tools that one will use in the future.  Now consider “Old Otto” following the onset of Alzheimer’s, but prior to the purchase of the notebook.  Still, the notebook lying on a store shelf never seen by Old Otto is not part of Old Otto’s cognitive apparatus.  How, then, does the notebook become part of Old Otto’s cognitive apparatus on a coupling argument?  One might suspect it begins with Otto’s coming to regularly use the apparatus.  It begins when Old Otto begins to manipulate his notebook.  But, it is right here that the coupling-constitution fallacy is committed.  It is committed when one makes the move to include new cognitive processing mechanisms, such as the notebook.  So, even Menary’s strong hypothesis that cognitive agents are never without their cognitive processes extending into tools is not enough to avoid the coupling-constitution fallacy.
Why isn't this a correct statement of Menary's view and also an adequate reply?

Now, later Menary comments, "I am not committed to the view that cognition is first
in the head and then gets extended into tools."  Right.  That's why we wrote,
"The suggestion appears to be that we should never think of a lone human being as a discrete cognitive system.  Humans are, so this line goes, always cognitive systems integrated into a network of interacting components.  Humans in their mere biological being are never cognitive systems.  Put more boldly, perhaps, insofar as humans are cognitive beings, they are essentially users of external vehicles."
Here is how our argument works though.  At t0 Otto is committed to one set of tools, hence not bereft of tools.  But, then at t1 he acquires a new tool, hence is still not bereft of tools.  At t1, Otto is now coupled to something else, but that new coupling does not make the processes that take place in that new tool cognitive processes.  So, we tweaked the C-C fallacy point to deal with change of tools used.  We are trying to give Menary this point, but show that it is of no help to him.  I don't see why this is otiose.

2 comments:

  1. I can't remember if I've asked you this; presumably things that actually do constitute a system of some kind are coupled. So while the coupling might not entail constitution, constitution requires coupling - correct?

    I was just wondering, because it seems as if extended cognition people have no choice but to have coupling involved, but that this by itself doesn't mean they're necessarily committing the fallacy, which is a separate question. Pointing out that Otto acquiring a new tool is a coupling moment then isn't enough to show that a fallacy has been committed; that only emerges if the coupling in question doesn't meet whatever requirements people want to impose to claim constitution (eg parity).

    ReplyDelete
  2. Yes, I assume that if you have a system, then its components will be coupled in some manner.

    You have to bear in mind here the nature of a fallacy, it's an argument in which the premises do not (deductively or inductively) support the conclusion. So, the A&A point is that showing that there is a coupling between, say, Otto's brainy thinking and his writing and reading of his notebook (while it might suffice to show that Otto + notebook is a kind of cognitive system), this would not support the conclusion that Otto's cognitive processing extends into his notebook or, if you prefer, that cognitive processes pervade the whole of the operations of the Otto + notebook system.

    So, A&A maintain that there is fallacy in moving from the coupling between Otto and notebook to the view that the entirely of the information processing in Otto + notebook is cognitive. To make the case for a principled basis for saying that Otto + notebook is not a cognitive processor throughout one can appeal to cognitive non-equivalence. (This is what we do in separate arguments.)

    One thing that has happened in the ten+ years, or so, that EC has bumping around is that we have now gotten past this charge of it being mere prejudice to think that the mind is in the head. I've not read an ECer writing that kind of thing in probably five years.

    ReplyDelete